Thursday, April 26, 2007

Virtual Reality

Martin Hunt headshot by Martin Hunt

A virtual reality is like a virtual image in a convex mirror - you really see it, but it isn't what it seems. Virtual reality has existed for decades as thought experiments and fiction. Lately, virtual reality has become real enough that you can actually walk around and explore a 3d space and interact with objects. In fact they have been common for some time now in computer games.

Let us leave the content of computer games aside for a moment and consider instead the experience of the game. What you experience is sights and sounds that can be responded to as if they were coming from objects and entities in an environment. The experience can be very engaging, to the point that for some it can be called an addiction.

I am familiar with several computer games, by no means the most advanced. "Titanic" is an interactive fiction piece. There is a clear story line: you are a British spy whose mission is to thwart some German spies. Your point of view is that a person walking around the ship. The events transpire on the night of the sinking. To win the game you have to solve a series of puzzles. The puzzles involve things like finding a crucial ring someplace on the ship. The ship itself is vividly represented and it is a pleasure to just explore, from the huge boilers at the bottom to the bridge at the top. The visuals and sounds combine with the narrative to create a vivid experience of reality.

Quake is similar in that you have a point of view that you manipulate through a 3d space. The difference is that the puzzles involve gaining skill as well as figuring things out. In Quake the environment that you explore is very vivid and often quite beautiful.

Age of Mythology is another game that I am familiar with, and it is different in type. Your point of view is that of a strategist high above a landscape. You get to move things around and build things. The idea is to build societies that can support armies that can beat enemies. It's a multilayered game involving economics and military strategy. As in other computer games, the visual experience is quite vivid.

These games are quite different from each other in many respects, but they are quite similar in the way that they engage a person's mind. You lose the sense of being a person looking at a computer screen with fingers on a keyboard. You really do come to feel that your are in a real space and are interacting with real objects there.

Computer games are designed to engage our minds to the extent that they create environments that we actually experience. It actually works very well. When I am on the Titanic, in the middle of the game, I am not experiencing a computer screen - I am experiencing a ship. This is very interesting - way more interesting than the games themselves. These games provide a way for us to probe our own minds so that we can understand how our minds give an experience of reality from sense datum.

The games I have mentioned are all interesting and engaging, but they are also fictions and constructions. They involve narratives that are shallow, and sometimes objectionable - they are games. I have recently started participating in a different sort of virtual reality. Its called Second Life, and it exists on the internet. It's not a game in the sense that the others are because there is no narrative, and there is no goal whereby one can win. Its a space that looks much like a computer game, but what one does there is build things (houses, sculptures, landscapes, etc) and talk to people. There is a real economy there. There are things to buy and sell. Second Life is way more interesting than a computer game. Watch this space.

Read More...

Monday, December 25, 2006

Emona

Martin Hunt headshot by Martin Hunt

From Martin Hunt's Fibonacci series of computer generated images.

Read More...

Friday, December 15, 2006

Spinors

Martin Hunt headshot by Martin Hunt

Spinors
A photograph of a lithograph produced by Martin Hunt.

Read More...

Tuesday, October 31, 2006

The Dismal Science

Martin Hunt headshot by Martin Hunt

Preamble

This article, "The Dismal Science", is a preliminary personal exploration of economics. I make no pretense that I know much about contemporary economic theory. I've tried to get into it a number of times but have always been repelled by (what is to me) the obvious idiocy of the economic thinking that I've encountered.

I see this as a paradigm problem. The ideas that make up the paradigm of mainstream economics just don't survive in the ecosystem of my mind, because they get attacked and destroyed, perhaps before I fully understand them.

It is obvious to me that I have my own understanding of economics - my own paradigm if you will - and that it is this paradigm that is blocking my acceptance of mainstream economic theory. But my own internal paradigm has never been brought fully into consciousness. While I hope that my paradigm is coherent, I must say in all honesty that I have never articulated it in a way that is complete enough to tell. I've decided to attempt that articulation.

Reading Thomas Kuhn has led me to believe that any paradigm, conscientiously explored, is better than no paradigm. One learns more by being clear, even if mistaken, than by being muddled. This exploration is an attempt to be clear enough that my mistakes will be obvious.

The Dismal Science

Economics has been called the "Dismal Science." My dictionary says that "dismal" means "gloomy, dreary, depressing, bleak." This definition certainly resonates at this time, at least here in British Columbia; it is getting harder and harder to make a living, and the provincial government is busily making it even harder. At every turn, when you seek answers to why this is happening -- the paraphrased answer is "Economics."

Personally, I think it a mistake to call Economics a dismal science because I don't think that it is a science, any more than theology is a science. In economics, as in theology, the central truth is assumed to be true (not demonstrated) and the whole conversation is dedicated to exploring the implications of that assumed truth and to various convoluted apologia whose purpose is to make the assumed truth seem more reasonable.

The Great Balance Sheet

In Economics, I think that the assumed truth is that an economy can be described by something like a balance sheet. This, it seems to me, is a result of the fact that economics has been concerned with money. Before things can even be thought of in economic terms, those things must have money values assigned to them. Once the money value is assigned then the thing can take its place as a number in the Great Balance Sheet.

If we ask the question "what is the proper money value of a thing?" we immediately confront the flaw in the balance sheet idea. The balance sheet is meaningless unless money values can be assigned, and the balance sheet takes on different states according to the actual money values assigned. Therefore the valuation of things determines crucially the information that a balance sheet provides.

Markets

I take it that the market is generally invoked as the means by which money value is assigned to things. In this context the market is seen as an external, objective reality beyond human control. The market is seen as automatically assigning values to things, in a way perhaps similar to the way that gravity naturally stratifies immiscible fluids of different densities within the same container. Just as no one tells the oil to float on water, supposedly no one fixes the price of a chocolate bar at a dollar -- it all just happens.

But with oil and water the relative densities are determined by physical details of atomic structure. There is no comparable physical fact that determines the value of a chocolate bar. What is the value of chocolate and peanuts? What is the value of the work that makes and distributes the chocolate bar?

Let's look at the value of chocolate. If I like chocolate, it has a high value -- if I don't like it, it has a low value. Thus, the effect of chocolate on the Great Balance Sheet depends on people's preferences. But how are preferences determined and measured? Supposedly, the market automatically and impersonally is affected by all the preferences and assigns a value for chocolate that reflects the average preference at any moment. The reason I say "supposedly" is that markets are obviously not affected by all preferences. Markets are only affected by those in a position to buy. The preferences of those who cannot buy are not, in general, influential on markets. Moreover, the preferences of those who buy a lot are much more influential than those who buy a little. Therefore it is clear that the money value that a market assigns to things is not determined by an average of all preferences, but by the preferences of a small subset of the population.

This seems very natural -- it is built into the logic of markets. It's only when we bring the assumed truth of economics, the Great Balance Sheet, into consciousness that the skewed valuation provided by markets is seen to be a problem. This is because the numbers that make the balance sheet meaningful are not really a true measure of value, but are instead just an assertion of the preferences of a small subset of a population. Thus the meaning that can be extracted from the Great Balance Sheet, presented as an objective representation of fact, is in fact a subtle but powerful promotion of the interests of those who are already rich against the interests of others with different needs and preferences. It is for this reason that economics, dismal as it may be, is nowhere near being a science. Of course a corollary of this is that the information provided by economics is not to be trusted.

I don't think that all markets are the same. Some do seem to provide a rational valuation. The market for chocolate bars would probably be a good example of this type. Due to wide voluntary participation in the market I'd bet that the selling price of chocolate bars is fairly directly linked to the costs of production and distribution, with a modest profit thrown in.

The valuation provided by some markets is determined more by issues of scarcity and popularity rather than by the cost of production. Most of the arts fall into this category. And while this may seem unjust to some, it does no great harm and makes a kind of sense. The labor market also falls into this category and in this case the result is not nearly so benign. Because the value of labor is not related to its costs, vast numbers of people are forced by their circumstances to sell their labor for less than the cost of their maintenance at a reasonable standard of living. This is what it means to be among the working poor. It is a hard cold fact that there are many people who cannot produce any value with their labour, and the labour market cannot provide any sustenance for such people. These are extremely serious issues about which the labour market has nothing to say.

The capital markets, that is the markets for stocks and bonds, are of a different type again. These are largely speculative markets driven by the desire to make money by means of financial manipulations rather than by production of any sort. Indeed, circumstances often arise where it is more profitable for the speculators to break up a productive resource than to maintain it. But more often this comes about because investment is not focussed on need but is rather driven by emotion and fear as the speculators seek to make something from nothing. Typically, the fact that speculators want something for nothing is disguised by the risks they take in their speculations. But the risk that speculators undertake is not a productive activity, even if it enables production. And -- let us not be blind -- speculation doesn't only enable production, it also inhibits production, because the reward to speculators in the form of interest and dividends is subtracted from the resources available for production as far as the Great Balance Sheet is concerned.

There is a certain irony here, for the speculators typically think of themselves as the source of wealth and production. Here is a quote from the Premier of British Columbia: "I'm surprised that they haven't figured out yet that it's private sector investment that actually generates the income that supports their jobs." I take a different view -- it is the work of people at their jobs that generates the wealth that private sector speculators rip off. When it comes right down to it, people at work are the only sources of wealth there are and it is this fundamental fact that the Great Balance Sheet makes invisible.

An interesting problem caused by the stock market arises because it causes productive entities to have two values -- the value of the company's assets minus its liabilities as its book value and the value of its stock to speculators as its stock value. Now apart from the fact that this double valuation further reinforces the idea that the Great Balance Sheet is not objectively meaningful, it is also very destructive. For instance, if speculative market forces cause the stock value to fall below its book value the company is vulnerable to being broken up by the speculators who hold its stock, even though the company is viable in other respects. When this happens it causes great harm and destruction. People lose their livelihoods and even if they regain it elsewhere later, the interval is still a time of loss, stress and suffering -- a price that they must pay so that speculators may profit. The very significant thing is that the suffering of such people never makes it onto the Great Balance Sheet and as far as economics is concerned is of no importance at all. To add insult to injury, economic theory seems to present such destruction as a positive thing -- a clearing out of deadwood that makes the economy more efficient -- as if the people involved were so much garbage.

Conclusion

So, the idea of the Great Balance Sheet causes a double distortion of our perception of economic reality. First it doesn't register non-monetary values, either positive or negative. Things like suffering caused by economic disruption don't get included in the conversation that the Great Balance Sheet informs. Neither do positive values, like (say) the satisfaction that people feel when they are secure, get entered into the Great Balance Sheet. Instead, these non-monetary values are used as the carrot and stick that causes most people to jump to the speculator's tune. The second distortion is that speculators, and it seems economists, tend to look at those who work in production as parasites -- a drain on wealth rather than as the source of wealth that they are. (See the quote from BC's Premier above.) This is extremely ironic of course, for the speculators really are parasitic.

I have a negative attitude about speculators. Perhaps it's obvious. I must qualify my negativity. First, and most important, I don't mean it personally. On a personal level, speculators are people who, for one reason or another, have a pool of value that is in excess to their needs that they are willing to let others use. Often enough, on a personal level, the hope of profit isn't the only or main reason why that value is made available. And often the pool of values that speculators possess was gathered by sacrifice and valuable work for which they had the good fortune to be rewarded. I do think that speculation is a bad social institution, but I also think that individual speculators must be seen as good or bad according to their circumstances, not because of their social role.

A second important point is to acknowledge the supreme importance of the existence of pools of capital and also to acknowledge the historic fact that speculation has been the primary and most effective way of accumulating such pools. Some would say therefore, that far from being negative, speculation is a positive boon that has brought us prosperity and freedom. I take a different view. It is clear to me that the potential benefits of pools of capital are not realized due to the wastage and ill-focused decision making that is characteristic of the speculative system. The best that can be said of speculation is that it serves as a bootstrap mechanism allowing pools of capital to form in the first place, but I believe that now that same mechanism has become an albatross around our collective neck, restricting our progress and driving us down dangerous paths.

If we have no speculators, what other system would accumulate pools of capital? This is a good question, the kind of question I'd hoped this paper would turn up, and a question for which I have no ready answer, yet.

Other good questions

Who or what should control the pools of capital. This is very vital. On the one hand, how do we ensure competent management so that the valuable pools are not frittered away? On the other hand, how do we prevent the controllers of those pools from turning into dictators if we discard the present anarchic system of many competing speculators?

In closing, what is the assumed idea upon which my own paradigm is based? What is it that I offer as a substitute for the Great Balance Sheet? I don't think that accounting, or even money, is what economics should be about. As a species, we have a task. That task is, bluntly, to support ourselves in the manner that we think fitting. The way we support ourselves is by working to extract the materials we need from our environment and by working to transform those materials into things that are useful to us. I think that economics is the study of how we support ourselves, how we propose to accomplish our great task.

Of course there are many different ways that we can support ourselves. We can set the task so that we are all subsistence farmers or we can set the task so that we are all participants in an industrial society. I don't think the choice of task we undertake is a matter of economics, it is more a matter of philosophy and ethics.

Read More...

Wednesday, October 11, 2006

Rationality and Intelligence

by Martin Hunt - copyright 2006 - All Rights Reserved

This article was included in the 37th issue of the Philosopher's Carnival.

One of the disconcerting things about science is that time and again the world is revealed to be not what we thought. The ancients did their best to account for the world that they saw. But their state of ignorance was such that many explanations (often conflicting) could account for what they knew. As knowledge is gained then the range of acceptable explanations diminishes. As we learn more, whole paradigms are shown to be invalid. This is an unpleasant outcome for the people who are committed to the invalid paradigms. They are faced with the necessity of abandoning a world view and adopting another. This is much more difficult than admitting error. When the world view is old, backed by tradition and community, then the transition to the new view is very difficult.

"The Robot's Rebellion" by Keith Stanovich is a book that proposes a very interesting and satisfying answer to the ancient puzzle; "How can a person (or anything for that matter) be 'free'?" A key concept in the Robot's Rebellion is the idea that comes from Richard Dawkins' book 'The Selfish Gene'. Dawkins' theme is that in biology the thing that replicates from generation to generation is genetic structure. The expression of the genetic structure - plants and animals - are not replicators. They are vehicles that carry the real replicators into the future.

Dawkins' idea is one of these disconcerting changes in perspective that I mentioned at the start of this essay. Previously it was assumed that the purpose of genes was to enable creatures to replicate. In the new view creatures exist to enable genes to replicate.

An important idea that came to us from the Greeks is that things have immaterial essences that determine their nature. Plato developed ideas about 'ideal form' - an immaterial template to which all actual examples conform. He figured that there was an 'ideal horse'; a perfect, but immaterial horse; and that all real horses were more or less flawed examples of that ideal horse. For Plato this wasn't just a verbal shorthand. He argued that the ideal horse was more real than the actual horses. Related to the idea of essence is the idea of spirit. Spirits were seen as the things that animate matter. Matter without spirit was just stuff - inanimate lumps. Matter with spirit was active - it moved around, did things, had intentions and desires.

At the time that these sorts of ideas were invented they represented an advance in understanding. It was an idea that was in accord with experience that enabled more and more experience to be understood - and even a flawed understanding is better than no understanding.

I think that ideas like 'soul' and 'mind' are associated with these Platonic understandings. A mind, or a soul, is seen as an immaterial entity that exists inside us and that controls or 'drives' the body. Basically, in the ancient conception, a mind drives a body the way that a person drives a car.

The problem with these ancient concepts is that they just don't accord to present knowledge. Hundreds of years of looking have never revealed anything like a soul or a mind. Moreover, contemporary science has found that there is no way for an immaterial mind to interact with a body - it violates fundamental principles like the conservation of matter and energy.

This is the context of 'Robot's Rebellion'. Stanovich is not concerned with interpreting the world in terms of the ancient concepts. The closest he comes to that is when, at the start of the book, he discusses how it is religious people who most vividly feel the incompatibility betweene the ancient and the new ways of thinking about what we are. What Stanovich is concerned with is laying out a more adequate structure for understanding.

He accepts the metaphor of the body as a vehicle - but he throws away the driver. Instead of having a driver, the vehicle is a robot charged with the task of figuring out _on_its_own_ how to get its passengers to their destination. The passengers are of course the replicators - the genes, and whatever replicators may be going along for the ride.

There are robots and robots. Some robots are directly programmed so that each stimulus has a preordained response. Such robots work pretty well in fixed environments like car assembly lines but don't work very well in an unstructured environment

Say you were taking an interstellar journey that would last several lifetimes where you would be placed in some sort of suspended animation until you arrived at your goal. Would you trust your fate to a hardwired robot of the assembly line type? Probably not - though it might work. What I would want is a robot that can figure out on its own how to satisfy my requirements. This is the sort of robot that people are - we are robots designed by evolution to figure out on its own how to satisfy the requirements of its passengers - genes. The genes have a bit of a problem - how to keep the robot loyal? Basically, Stanovich's idea is that people are robots that can be disloyal to their masters - Rebellious Robots.

How could disloyalty come about? How can anything like a vehicle gain autonomy? Autonomy is different from freedom. Freedom means causeless effects. Putting aside the question of whether causeless effects are even possible I ask instead - would you want your actions to be uncaused? Would you trust yourself to walk down a street knowing that you might, as a bus approached, leap in front of it - for no reason at all? That's the sort of thing that freedom implies.

Evolution is a process that causes the best replicators to populate the future. Could genes alone have produced autonomous vehicles? It is hard to see how. Even if genes had foresight, and wanted their vehicles to be autonomous - its hard to imagine how they would do it. And, it must be acknowledged, genes have no foresight.

This is a problem that is quite general. For instance, any king with an ambassador faces the problem of the rebellious robot. Kings have been able to deal with this problem with various degrees of success. Kings tend to be very smart. How can a gene, which isn't smart at all, cope with this problem? Genes have an strategy not based on the mind - they either replicate or they don't - genes don't care one way or another. But with variation, genes can explore a huge possibility space, and in time can stumble upon all sorts of unlikely solutions.

How is it that a robot can rebel? This is possible if the capabilities built into it enable developments that the builders could not foresee. It was Dawkins, again in 'The Selfish Gene', who suggested a way that this could happen. He proposed that genes aren't the only possible replicators. The new replicator that he described depends on the capacity for imitation. Imitation is very similar to replication. With genetics, genes are replicated. With imitation, behaviour is replicated. Dawkins wondered whether there were circumstances where imitation would support the evolutionary algorithm - as genetic replication does. It turns out that imitation would indeed support an evolutionary algorithm.

Dawkins proposed, and Susan Blackmore and others have elaborated on this idea. The replicating ideas are called memes, and the study of the implications of memes is called memetics. The presence of memes in a brain means that a body is host to two independent sets of replicators - genes and memes. Genes evolve to produce creatures. Memes evolve to produce minds, and language, and culture. A creature with a mind is responding to two necessities - genetic necessities and memetic necessities.

A mind like ours needs to be both intelligent and rational. Rationality allows the construction and manipulation of fairly abstract mental structures. Intelligence determines the scope and effectiveness of mental structures and also the speed of their creation.

In an autonomous robot there are many systems that behave automatically, beyond both the robot's direct control. These systems are very useful, and essential for autonomy - but they aren't themselves autonomous. Low level systems like perception are among this collection of automatic systems. So are mid-level systems that generate our thoughts and utterance. And higher level automatic systems might create capacities like intelligence and creativity. At the very top of this hierarchy is consciousness.

It is easy to be very mysterious about consciousness, but this doesn't get us anywhere. Let us accept a non-mysterious concept of consciousness and work from there. Consciousness is an ability that rests on a lower ability - the ability to generate a narrative. A narrative is a description of a sequence of events. A particular kind of narrative presents the events as a causal chain - these are explanations. Consciousness, I suggest, is a particular kind of explanatory narrative - its a narrative that tells the creature what is going on around it. An extension of consciousness is self-awareness - the creature is aware of its own role in the narrative that it is both generating and listening to.

Memes are of crucial importance for narratives. All but the simplest narratives depend on words, and words depend on memes. A simple narrative that doesn't need words might be seen when a creature does something with unpleasant consequences. The non-verbal narrative might be expressed in words as "ooo! - bad outcome! - avoid this kind of situation!" A higher level narrative is when a creature produces the narrative upon observing another creature. A higher level narrative is when a creature can imagine itself in a situation and what would happen.

Now all of this narrative creation can be completely automatic. But it enables a surprising and new thing. It allows competing narratives to be created, and behaviour can be caused by the interpretation and evaluation of those competing narratives. When behaviour is determined by evaluation of circumstances - then behaviour is autonomous. I think that this is the source of autonomy in the world.

Let us note the source of the autonomy. It is not something created by genes. Nor is it something created by memes. It is something that is created by an environment where genes and memes are co-creating a creature. The capacities that genes and memes build into their creatures surprisingly merge in a way that enables the creature to transcend their creators.

That we can transcend the interests of creators and pursue goals of our own is the surprising outcome or the co-evolution of genes and memes. All of our mental capacities are important in this. BUT - (big but) - rationality is key. The reason for this is that it is rationality that produces reliable descriptions of the way that reality may evolve from the present - either into the future or into the past. There are other ways (irrational) of producing such descriptions - but such descriptions are not found to be reliable.

We thus come to a crucial distinction between intelligence and rationality. Intelligence makes us better or worse at attaining our goals - whatever those goals might be. Intelligence, per se, doesn't provide guidance about what the goals should be. Rationality does, potentially, have the ability to evaluate goals. Rationality allows us to step back and ask "Do I want to do this?"

For a hundred years our culture has been obsessive about the value of intelligence and has been more or less disrespectful towards rationality. We have very smart people working towards bad goals. This is not a desired outcome. Better, I suggest, to focus our attention on rationality.

This blog is called Reason and Rhyme. Let us cherish both. Reason is rationality - the capacity we have for making sense of the world. Rhyme is for our other essential capacities - intelligence, creativity, sensitivity - that makes living fun.

Both are pretty important.

Read More...

Saturday, September 30, 2006

Terrorism: What Is it?

author - September 2003
by Martin Hunt

Most of us agree that terrorists are murderous bastards. But there are many sorts of murderous bastards. Are all murderous bastards terrorist? The Beltway snipers from a few years ago sure did spread terror - but should they be placed in the same category as suicide bombers motivated by bad religion and oppression?

Nobody doubts that the attack on 9/11 was a terrorist attack. The attack on Baghdad in the spring of 2003 was a terrorist attack too. The very term used to describe the strategy by the Pentagon; "Shock and Awe", refers to the terror that the US leaders hoped to create among Iraqis in order to minimize their resistance to invasion. The "Shock and Awe" image is particularly disturbing, because for a long time the Western democracies had tried to not be terrorists - UN peacekeeping missions were the opposite of terrorism - people risking their lives in very difficult situations to try and make populations feel safe enough to resume normal life.

Nobody doubts that suicide bombers are terrorist weapons. The point of terror is to make people scared that they will be killed or mutilated as they innocently go about their daily business. This fear is supposed to generate a political instability that will cause old power structures to collapse and new ones to arise. In this view the Beltway Snipers, terrifying as they were, were not terrorists - they were extortionists - guys out for a quick buck.

We forget that terror, as a weapon, has a long history. Israel wouldn't exist without the terrorist atrocities committed by Zionists led by Menachim Begin 50 years ago. The British were driven from Palestine by terror. A friend of mine's father was there at the time, as a British soldier. He tells of Zionists murdering people, and then booby trapping their bodies with bombs to also get the ambulance crew. My point here isn't to vilify Israel -- its only to point out that terrorism isn't only a vile tactic used against us by outsiders. Terrorism is a weapon that has been used by the ruthless through the ages - and all peoples and nations have their fair share of ruthless and violent people clawing after power, for whatever reason.

There is another aspect of terrorism that we often forget. The American people were understandably traumatized by the events of 9/11. Much of the world was traumatized by that. But surely it must be acknowledged that a large proportion of the trauma grew out of the presentation of those terrible events on TV. Hour after hour, day after day, people saw those planes slamming into those towers. Hour after hour we saw photos of the victims in the tower hurtling to the ground. I still have an image in my mind of a bald guy in mid air - head pointed to the ground, his body curled into a fetal position. My point here is that that kind of coverage magnifies the terror generated by the events tremendously.

So, in the contemporary world, some governments are using terrorist acts done by others to terrorize its own population into passive obedience. Even now, five years down the road we live in a situation where governments use terrorist acts as an excuse to do whatever they want. According to recent reports, Donald Rumsfield was agitating for an attack on Iraq the day after 9/11. He'd been wanting to do that for years, and here was his excuse. My view is that a government that uses terror in this way is itself using terror as a tool - my definition of terrorism above covers this situation very neatly.

On 9/11 al Quaeda carried out a terrorist action against the USA, and more broadly against all of the open societies in the world. I'm not particularly clear about what al Quaeda hoped to accomplish with such an act. But it is clear that many people have seized upon that attack as an excuse to transform democracy. I think that its not unreasonable to say that these people are actually trying to destroy democracy as we know it by instituing such a severe regime of security and secrecy that the citizens will not be well enough informed about their society to be able to make rational decisions.

For me, terrorism is a weapon. Weapons are used in war. I don't think that terrorism, as a weapon, is any worse than cruise missiles, atomic bombs, invasion forces or any of the other military capabilities possessed by the governments of the world. It would be nice to say that terror is too inhumane to be used because it kills so many non-combatants. All warfare kills non-combatants, and all warfare terrorizes non-combatants. It's a bit too cute to single out terrorism as intolerable while we think of the rest as being honorably military.

I have an extreme abhorrence for terrorists. For me though, George Bush is the biggest terrorist in the world. Ariel Sharon is a terrorist too. Just this summer, in Lebanon, we witnessed a war where both sides were obviously terrorsts - attacking each other's civilian populations to try and force political change. Osama Bin Laden is a terrorist also, but a minor one - one created in fact by the US in Afghanistan in the 1980's. Bin Laden is a traitor of course in that he has turned against his sponsors. But he's not the big guy.

I sure hope that this will not be construed as an anti-American rant. It's not my intention. My intention is merely to point out that if we are to resist the anti-democratic direction that our society is going that a lot of people will have to realize that they are being emotionally manipulated to have a "knee-jerk" reaction to whatever the government chooses to label "terrorist". We need to resist this manipulation and regain our perspective. If we allow democracy to be destroyed, then we will have thrown away something of tremendous value in a futile effort to be "safe". Our biggest protection is our democratic values. If we throw away our liberty then we will not be safe.

Read More...