Wednesday, November 08, 2006

The Organization of Sensory Experience into Sensory Spaces and Their Coordination with Physical Space

Huntley Ingalls headshot by Huntley Ingalls

Abstract

Visual, kinesthetic, and tactual sensory fields, visual afterimages, and dreams have spatial characteristics, although physical space is commonly considered to be the only real space. Characteristics of non-physical spaces will be described using the concept of sensory spaces, which was introduced by the French mathematician Henri Poincaré at the beginning of the twentieth century. Poincaré argued that space should not be conceived of as an immutable medium containing objects and events, but as a field of operations that is supported by a variety of processes and operations and the laws by which they succeed one another. The coordination of sensory spaces with physical space will be discussed by approaching the idea of space through the mathematical concept of a manifold--an idea more fundamental than space, which is a type of manifold. This approach facilitates a deeper understanding of the nature of spaces, the ways in which spaces are generated, and how sensory and dream spaces have extension that does not conflict with the extension of physical space.

Visual, tactual, and kinesthetic sensory experiences, visual afterimages, and dreams have distinct spatial characteristics. The relation of these spaces to physical space is a difficult issue in the philosophy of perception. How can sensory images and dreams have spatial features and how can such spaces coexist with physical space, which is commonly assumed to be the only real space? Clear insights into these difficulties are possible through ideas on the nature of space that have been developed by intensive geometrical research in the last 150 years. A favorable ground for pursuing these ideas can be prepared by considering the development of spatial concepts and operations in children or congenitally blind people whose sight has been restored by surgery. This can relieve the constraints of mistaken attitudes and preconceptions about the nature of space that make confusion almost inevitable.

Piaget's research shows that the child's concept of space begins with an almost undifferentiated flux and is built up through several very definite and revealing stages.1These stages include: the recognition of certain constant combinations of features and patterns; the ability to follow a moving object and recognize the invariance of its form despite its movement; the understanding that an operation, such as hiding an object, can be undone by a second operation; and the child's discovery that he can go from A to B by many paths, and if this is done by any one path he can undo it by many alternate paths. At the end of these stages the child acquires a mental map of the world with a set of permanent places occupied by various objects, one of which is himself from which there is a unique perspective on the world. Later these concepts of space are extended to the refinements of perspective, topological relationships, and geometrical thought. This map pervades perception so intimately that it seems to be an inevitable and necessary feature of experience, and it becomes nearly impossible to question its basic nature.

Congenitally blind people whose sight has been restored by surgery experience great difficulty perceiving three-dimensional space and the relations between objects. They are able to see little at first, and cannot name objects or distinguish between simple objects and shapes. The visual field is a confused pattern of light, dark, colored, and moving visual sensations that bear little resemblance to the visual field of a normal person. They tend to see only the outlines of solid geometrical figures; for example, a sphere appears to be the same as a disk. There is usually a long period of learning before the formerly blind can develop useful vision, and in some cases this is never accomplished. Some give up the attempt and revert to a life of blindness, often after a period of severe emotional distress. Some quickly learn to see rather well; particularly those who are intelligent, active, and who have received a good education while blind. One of these, a man who had been blind from the ages of 10 months to 52 years, enjoyed making things with simple tools and longed for a time when he might see. He tried throughout his life to picture the visual world. When his bandages were removed he did not suddenly see the world of objects as a normal person does. He was able to use his eyes well after a few days and judge distances and sizes accurately if he already knew a particular object by touch, although his sense of vertical distance was much distorted. He was unable to recognize objects that he had not touched and was unable to draw anything he did not already know by touch. His tactual and kinesthetic experience had enabled him to develop a sense of space which, after some effort, could be transferred to his newly acquired vision.2This research confirms the ideas of the French mathematician Henri Poincaré, who wrote in the early twentieth century that isolated sensations cannot provide an individual with a concept of space; rather, this is developed through learning the laws by which these sensations succeed one another, especially in response to the voluntary movements of the individual.3Space is a concept that is abstracted from physical operations, and not a static medium containing objects.

The concept of sensory spaces becomes more accessible through the mathematical idea of a manifold. The concept of a manifold is more general than that of space, which is a subset of manifolds. It enables us to develop basic ideas that are fundamental to the concept of space. Since the idea of a manifold is more abstract and unfamiliar than that of space, we do not approach it with the same ingrained attitudes we have about space. This enables us to bypass some of our preconceptions and permits a fresh and powerful perspective on the concept of space.

Manifolds

The location of any book in a bookcase can be specified by two descriptions; for example, third shelf from the top, eighth book from the left. The location of any bead in a string of beads can be specified by a single description, such as eleventh bead from the left. A manifold is any set of elements such that the location of any element in the set is completely specified when all of n essential descriptions are given. The elements may be objects, operations, or anything specifiable, and the description may be any clearly defined characteristic that is variable, such as distance, brightness, or weight. A manifold is connected if for any two of its elements there exists a chain or path between them such that every element of the path is a member of the manifold. The string of beads is connected; the shelved books are not because there is no path of books between the shelves. A connected manifold is discrete if a passage along a path in the manifold encounters abrupt changes in the varying characteristics; otherwise it is continuous. For example, movement along a string of beads, or through a series of Morse code sounds, encounters sudden changes between the elements. The colors of the spectrum, or the muscular sensations of extending an arm, form a continuous series of gradations into other colors or muscular sensations.

A manifold is one-dimensional if the removal of a single element divides it into two parts such that there is no unbroken path between the parts. A manifold is two-dimensional if the removal of a one-dimensional manifold divides it in a similar manner. It is n-dimensional if it is necessary to remove an (n-I)-dimensional manifold in order to divide it.4For example, a succession of musical notes of continuously varying pitch is a one-dimensional manifold, because the removal of a note in the succession makes any passage through it encounter a sudden jump in pitch. If each note can be sounded with both varying pitch and intensity, two descriptions are necessary to specify a sound, and we now have a two-dimensional manifold. The removal of a single note will not cut it into two parts. A one-dimensional manifold must be removed; for example, all notes at middle C in all its intensities. Any path between notes less than and greater than the removed pitch would encounter a sudden jump. Similarly, each note may be varied in tone to form a three-dimensional manifold.5

Continuous connected manifolds are very common in ordinary life. The shades of gray between black and white, and the spectrum of weights between two given weights are one-dimensional manifolds.6The color continuum is a three-dimensional manifold of hue, saturation, and brightness. A sensory manifold is any manifold that depends on the stimulation of a definite set of sense organs in a particular individual. The sensory manifolds are especially significant for the idea of sensory spaces.

Suppose a person is blindfolded and his skin touched with two pin points. That person can distinguish between the points if there is sufficient spread between them, but when they are brought together they are felt as one point. From any tactual point on the skin there is a path of such points to any other tactual point on the skin; that is, there exists a one-dimensional manifold of tactual points between any two such points on the skin. Now consider a continuous series of such points encircling the arm, and then imagine that they have been removed. All the tactual points have now been divided into two distinct domains, the points that are on the lower arm and those on the rest of the body. All paths between points in these two areas are broken by the series that was removed. It is necessary to remove a one-dimensional manifold of tactual points from the skin in order to divide it into two separate domains of tactual points. The set of all tactual points on the body is a two-dimensional sensory manifold.

Visual manifolds are more complex. The basic visual field is two-dimensional. Visual elements are directly perceived to the right and left and above and below the direction of sight. Objects are also perceived at various distances from the eyes, but this third dimension of the visual field does not have the simple direct quality of the other two. Otherwise, the far side of opaque objects would be visible. The visual elements are assigned distance values according to a complex set of cues, such as muscular accommodation in the eye, hue, brightness, superposition, perspective, and texture-density gradients. The visual elements are distributed in a two-dimensional field, but the cues assign a third characteristic to the elements which makes the visual experience a three-dimensional field. Turning the head or walking generates a continuous family of visual fields which are integrated into a single system. Such activity adds parallax shift, which is an additional distance cue. The family of visual fields arising from the observer's movements and past experiences is integrated into a common manifold. The various descriptions specifying the location of elements in this integrated family of visual fields can always be reduced to three independent descriptions.

The set of feelings that corresponds to the various stages of contraction of a muscle is a one-dimensional manifold. All of the families of muscular sensations are integrated into a common three-dimensional kinesthetic manifold. Two different kinds of sensory manifolds can be combined into a common manifold, and the equivalence values between the two kinds of sensory elements reduce its dimensionality. For example, vision and the handling of objects are coordinated into a visual-kinesthetic manifold. When one reaches for an object, the hand is seen to touch it exactly when the arm is felt to be sufficiently extended. No more than three descriptions, visual or kinesthetic, are needed to specify any element of this system. For example, the location of an object may be described by saying "Walk thirty paces forward, then fifty paces to the left, then look up eight feet."The system is further elaborated by incorporating values from other senses, such as tactual and auditory ones. All the senses are integrated into a three-dimensional general sensory manifold.

Spaces

Connected manifolds are the essence of space. Understanding space through this concept provides a perspective of its basic nature that is free of misleading preconceptions. A space is a connected manifold such that each element has associated with it subsets of elements called neighborhoods. A neighborhood may be thought of loosely as a region of elements having the same general properties as the manifold. For example, any small region on the surface of a sheet of paper is a two-dimensional manifold similar to the two-dimensional manifold of the entire sheet. The elements are called points, and the kind of space depends on the particular axioms that the neighborhoods satisfy. The most familiar spaces, when idealized, satisfy the following conditions:

  1. Each point has at least one neighborhood. point and neighborhood
  2. Any two neighborhoods of the same point have a common subset, which is a neighborhood of that point. point neighborhoods subset
  3. If the point y is contained in a neighborhood of the point x, there exists a neighborhood of y, which is a subset of the neighborhood of x. point subsets
  4. For any two distinct points there exist two neighborhoods without common points. points distinct neighborhoods

The familiar space of normal life satisfies these conditions. Visual, tactual, and kinesthetic manifolds are less stable,7Yet, as they are experienced, they generally satisfy these axioms and are sensory spaces. We have seen that the sensory manifolds are integrated into a more complex manifold of sensations, memories, and abstract manifolds to form a more stable general sensory manifold. This manifold satisfies the axioms more consistently, and it is a space.

The neighborhood axioms outline the connectivity properties of a space, that is, their topology. A metric space is a space in which all pairs of points have a well-defined distance relation.8For example, the separation of any two points in the space of a room may be expressed in centimeters.

Consider an extended one-dimensional space whose elements are points of light consecutively ordered by increasing brightness. Each element is uniquely situated in the space by its brightness specification, but it is not necessary to designate a brightness value in order to locate an element uniquely. The nth brightness is also simply the nth element. A position can be associated with every element of the space, and the set of all positions is itself a space. Such second order spaces can be associated with primary spaces of any dimensionality, and the corresponding spaces have identical mathematical characteristics. We can think of such abstract spaces as background for the primary elements. This provides us a powerful basic system as a reference for the primary elements. The background space is abstracted from the primary elements and their relations. They can no more stand alone than the current of a river can flow without water, although it is very expedient to work with the abstract properties of spaces as with purely mathematical hydrodynamics. In the sensory spaces we have an operational awareness of both primary elements and abstract positions. The general sensory manifold is a very complex unity of concrete and abstract spaces.

The operational experiences of ordinary life support a concept of universal space that incorporates all the sensory spaces into a general frame of reference for the familiar world. This is what is thought of as public or physical space. It is the space referenced in describing places, shapes, and locations to other people. Physical space has many advantages over sensory space. It is not centered in the individual. It incorporates a lifetime of experienced sensory spaces and includes the ground of possible sensory spaces that have not been experienced. It is far more consistent and dependable than sensory spaces. Unlike sensory spaces it is homogeneous and isotropic.9A very important characteristic of physical space is represented by the postulate that the interval between any two points on a rigid rod remains independent of any motion of the rod, thus enabling consistent measurements.

This line of development is continued in geometry by considering a mathematical space that is an idealization of physical space. It is then possible to study the purely logical properties of this ideal space. While Euclidean geometry appears to represent physical space quite well, mathematicians have constructed other internally consistent spaces. It is possible that some non­Euclidean geometry could be a better model of the physical universe on a cosmological scale. Pure mathematicians even postulate spaces that have no relation to the physical world. They are concerned only with the purely mathematical properties of these ideal constructions.

Physical space and time are commonly thought of as systems of infinitesimal points and instants, but these are concepts of ideal mathematical space and time. Empirical spaces differ from such ideal spaces. A person's vision has a lower limit of acuity, although there is no awareness of the grain of the visual field. The cell assemblies that operate as functional units in the retina, lateral geniculate body, and visual cortex suggests that the sensory fields do not function in the same manner as operations performed on isolated independent points. The operational elements of the sensory fields are not the momentary elementary sensations described by the

structuralists, but are entities such as line segments, corners, or vowels, which reflect the pattern of neural operations. Infinitesimal points and instants are essential concepts in the mathematical analysis of the ideal spaces of geometry and physics, but they are misleading for sensory spaces. Physicists have considered the possibility that even physical space and time are not composed of infinitesimal elements.

Human perceptions do not arise from operations on points of from momentary sensations. An overall structure is built up and abstracted from looser and more expanded elements, from which points and instants can then be constructed. The smallest elements common to the overlapping of the operational units of sensory space define its points. These natural units can then be redefined in terms of points. Thus, the operational priority of the units becomes replaced by the structural priority of points, which misleadingly suggests that points have operational priority. Isolated sensations are not elementary experiences. However, ideal concepts have mistakenly led to the structuralist school of perception.

One of the features most intimately associated with the familiar space of ordinary life is extension. Extension is not the same as distance. Time is not extended in the manner of space, yet it satisfies the conditions of the distance relation. Extension is regarded as such a universal and convincing characteristic of the space of human experience that it is considered to pervade throughout the world and encompass all of existence. This belief is problematic in the philosophy of perception, and makes it necessary to understand the nature of extension and its implications for sensory spaces.

A space is extended if it satisfies the following conditions:

  1. All pairs of elements have separation; this is the last of the four neighborhood axioms.
  2. All elements exist simultaneously.
  3. For any two elements, and any path within the space connecting them, there is a possible operation for traversing that path by a movement that acquires the specifications of each element as it is encountered.

The first condition is the basis of the idea of "here," "there," and "a partness." The second condition is partially the basis for the strong feeling of reality and stability associated with ordinary space. From the vantage point of any part of an extended space, other parts are considered to be there now. The third condition provides the feeling of access, in principle, to all parts of an extended space. These conditions are not only satisfied by physical space, but also by the visual, tactual, and kinesthetic fields and by general sensory space.

A series of objects of continuously increasing weight has separation and simultaneity, but there is no movement from one weight to another that acquires the varying weights. There can be the implied movement that results from changes in attention, but attention is not the same as weight.

Voluntary movements are critical to the development of the concept of extended space because access, in principle, is a fundamental feature of such space. Thus the kinesthetic manifold is a uniquely important subspace of the general sensory manifold. One can directly control and change separate parts of kinesthetic space at will, allowing an ease of direct access to all its parts unmatched by the space of other senses. This feature generates a feeling of being a part of physical space while the other senses provide a feeling of observing it. In kinesthetic perception an object can actually be surrounded by a system of muscular movements. The object then appears to be embedded in a space generated by the movements of the body. This special characteristic of kinesthetic space is incorporated into general sensory space which is then generalized into physical space.

The imagery in dreams that are clear not only satisfies the criteria for space, but also for extended space. Dream spaces are usually extended in three dimensions, with separation, simultaneity, and voluntary movement among the elements. The philosopher H.H. Price described the spatial relations of dream images in vivid language:

If I dream of a tiger, my tiger-image has extension and shape. The dark stripes have spatial relations to the yellow parts, and to each other; the nose has a spatial relation to the tail. Again, the tiger-image as a whole may have spatial relations to another image in my dream, for example to an image resembling a palm tree.10

It is common in dreams for a person to walk down a path, cross a bridge, see a face, look into a canyon, or approach some object of interest, all of which are spatial experiences in the dream.

Physical space is commonly regarded as a unique medium in which all of existence is embedded. This implies that there can be no extended spaces other than physical space, and hence that dream and sensory spaces are unreal or paradoxical. The imagery in dreams has extension, yet the extension of a dream space cannot be extension in physical space. This paradox is resolved by the realization that space is nothing more than a special kind of organization of elements. A system of elements may be a space under the organization of one domain, but not a space when viewed through the organization of a different domain. The source of a dream space is neural events occurring in physical space, but the geometric relations in dream space are not geometric relations in physical space. A pair of independent radiophoto transmissions occurs in the same space from the viewpoint of the physical world, but there are two image spaces from the viewpoint of the organizations within the signal variations. There is a basis in physical space for the image spaces, but that basis is only a play of signal variations when viewed within the geometry of physical space. What is space from one organizational vantage point may be only a collection of disordered elements from another. Thus it is possible that dreams and drug visions, which are extended spaces, can have an electrochemical basis in the brain and yet be completely unrecognizable as images and spaces from an ordinary physical point of view.

Extension in dreams does not conflict with the extension of physical space, because the elements and operations in dreams are not a recognizable submanifold of physical space. A dream manifold is not merely a simulation of extension. The third dimension supported by perspective and other cues in a painting is a simulation of extension, because there can be no access movement in that dimension except through changes in attention. There is motion in the third dimension in a movie, but there is no way for that motion to be accessible. It is possible to control movement in the third dimension of a mirror, but the source of that control is not within the image space. The image space is extended in a third dimension in accordance with the image behavior, but the source of movement is not in that space. Dream spaces are usually extended in three dimensions, but sometimes only in two, and there is separation, simultaneity, and voluntary movement among the elements. Unlike the case of images in a mirror, in a dream the source of movement is within the space. The visual, tactual, kinesthetic, and general sensory spaces also have genuine extension, and their association with physical space is sufficiently close to support the common attitude that those extensions are somehow part of the extension of physical space. Approaching the concept of space by means of the idea of manifolds clearly shows how it is possible for spaces to exist within spaces, that have no common organization except from a perspective outside the system.

The idea that the familiar extended space of ordinary experience is generated by events and is not a unique and eternal medium in which objects are immersed is startling to common sense. The complex of sensory and physical spaces and their second-order fields, which are ordinarily termed "space," has such a comprehensive framework that it is difficult to show that space is not an immutable medium without implicitly assuming such a medium. Our spatial framework is so constantly present and familiar that when we attempt to imagine it in the absence of operations, a second order field remains before us and we speak of "empty space." But that space is not truly empty. We have subtly intruded unconscious attitudes into it, which support that space. Thus space is usually construed to be an absolute entity. Liebnitz thought of space as "an order of coexistences"but this idea was two hundred years ahead of its time.

Generation of Sensory Spaces

The mutability of the sensory spaces is more readily apparent. Tactile space is abolished when the body is immersed in water at body temperature and sensation is nullified. When all muscular activity ceases, the kinesthetic space of the moment is nothing more than rather vague attitudes associated with previous muscular experience, and thus it is clear that kinesthetic space is entirely dependent on muscular activity. It becomes clear that the third dimension of visual space is generated, when we perceive the effects of altering basic depth cues by optical instruments or reversed lighting. A different three-dimensional space is then experienced, which may have exaggerated depth, be stretched out, or reversed. When a person first wears new eyeglasses, his visual and kinesthetic coordination are initially upset. The street may look closer than his sensations indicate. His general sensory space is distorted by altered correlations until he is able to learn a new system. The basic two-dimensional field is never absent in the waking state, but the deterioration of acuity toward the edges of the field and the phenomenon of the blind spot reveal that it is generated.

Physical space is less mutable than general sensory space, yet modern physics has shown that physical space is not independent of physical processes. It is distorted under the extreme conditions considered by relativity theory. The geometric properties of physical space are determined by matter and its transformations.

Some sensory spaces have the character of a medium, which is any definite kind of entity distributed in the manner of an extended space. A painting is supported by the medium of paint. The momentary visual field is the medium of visual sensations. Kinesthetic space is not a medium, because its extension is supported not by muscular sensations alone but by those sensations and attitudes about possible muscular sensations. General sensory space is a fabric of sensory media, operations, and attitudes. Physical space is a manifold of physical transformations and their second order spaces. Physical space is not a medium, but our means of conceptualizing it subtly projects it on imaginary media. The visual field is a very strong source of this projection. The tendency to think of physical space as a kind of nothingness which is yet a medium contributes to the confusion felt when we try to imagine the limits of a finite physical universe. None of the higher-order spaces is a medium, because the elements have only mathematical properties.

Spaces have no independent substance of their own. All are dependent in various ways on first-order elements and their relations. The main difference between the spatiality of sensations and that of objects is the degree of refinement to which metrics can be assigned to them. Ideas of physical space are developed by means of experiences with physical entities. As Poincaré observed, the body is a crude measuring instrument, and the instruments that the child owes to nature and those the scientist owes to his ingenuity have the same fundamental basis in the solid body and the light ray.11Physical space has no properties independent of the instruments used to measure it, and to geometrize is to study their properties.

The familiar extended spaces have a smooth contiguity from region to region that appears to be one of their immutable features. Yet the visual field has a lower limit of acuity, although we are not aware of boundaries or gaps between the visual elements. Direct scrutiny of the visual field is incapable of detecting them because they do not exist for that operation, just as one cannot feel the roughness between the grains of sandpaper. Any operation that traverses a set of elements in such a way that gaps are undetectable has a smooth continuity for that operation.12A time lapse movie of a door in which each frame shows only a closed door may have gaps in which the door is open, but that will be completely invisible in the film and only a smooth continuous sequence of a closed door will be apparent. Areas that are contiguous in one operation may not be with respect to another. It is possible to construct a set of contiguous areas on a flat surface which are in separate planes situated at various distances when viewed in a stereoscope.

The Pulfrich pendulum illusion is an elegant demonstration of the neural system's ability to generate space. Cover one eye with a dark transparent glass and let a pendulum that consists of a weight and a string several feet long swing in a straight arc perpendicular to the line of sight. When the oscillating bob is viewed with both eyes, it appears to circumscribe an ellipse. The eye that is adapted to the dark takes a longer time to integrate energy and send messages to the brain; hence it sees the bob slightly in the past. The disparity in the effective position of the two eyes generates an ellipse which the bob appears to trace in its swings. The time discrepancy is equivalent to a binocular parallax effect which, for the brain, is exactly as if the bob were really swinging in an ellipse. Julasz's random dot stereograms create another effect that vividly demonstrates the ability of the central nervous system to generate space. These are special pairs of displays constructed with a computer in such a way that each display consists of random dots with no recognizable structure, but when viewed stereoscopically they are perceived as a geometrical structure lying in depth. These spaces are not in the physical optics of the situation, but in the organization of sensory input by the neural system. Such clearly constructed purely synthetic spaces have the same basic quality as the spaces of ordinary experience, and there is a continuous spectrum of spatial experiences between them.

Sensory spaces are not known by direct apperception, but are generated by neural activity coordinated with surrounding physical space. Much of sensation is not experienced at the location of the nerves that support it. This is vividly illustrated by the amputee's experience of the phantom limb. The colors that are induced by the flicker of a strobe seem to be in front of the face, not at the retina or visual cortex. This disparity between the location of a nerve and its sensation indicates that the whole field of a person's sensation is a projection, for there is no difference between the sensation of a nerve stimulated in these unusual ways and one that has been simulated by natural agents.

The topology of the neural network and its events has no necessary resemblance to the topology of the sensory experiences. The physical events in the brain that support sensory or dream space may be highly scattered, but the operations between them give the feeling of contiguity which is spatially convincing. The source of sensory spaces is neural events in physical space, but their geometry is not in physical space.

The union of general sensory space and physical space is the ordinary space experienced in daily life. The familiar world is the union of ordinary space and experience which has location in this space. Dreams and drug deliriums are not in the ordinary external world, but their spaces can be so well developed that the perspective of objects actually changes to correspond with the movements of the observer within them. Hallucinations are false perceptions that appear to be located in ordinary space. Visual afterimages are an interface between visual and physical spaces. They have definite locations in the immediate two-­dimensional visual manifolds, but not in the three-dimensional general sensory space or in physical space.

Conclusion

A manifold is an ordered assemblage of elements each uniquely located by exactly n specific descriptions. Space is a special kind of manifold. Spaces are of many varieties from Poincaré's sensory spaces to ideal mathematical spaces, dream spaces, and hybrid spaces such as general sensory space. Understanding spaces as manifolds clearly shows how spaces can be distorted, and generated, and how sensory and dream spaces can have extension which does not conflict with the extension of physical space.


1 J. Piaget, The Origin of Intelligence in the child, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1953. J. Piaget and B Inhelder, The Child's Conception of Space, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1956.

2 M. Von Senden, Space and Sight, trans. P. Heath, Methuen-Free Press, 1960. R.L. Gregory and J.G. Wallace, "Recovery from early blindness: a case study," Exp. Psychol. Soc. Monograph No.2, Cambridge, 1963.

3 Henri Poincaré, Mathematics and Science: Last Essays, Chs. 2 and 3, Dover, New York, 1963.

4 For our purposes, we do not need to consider the problems of higher con nectivities. For example a circle is a one-dimensional manifold of points but two points must be removed to cut it into two parts. Any n dimensional manifold such that the removal of a single n-i dimensional manifold cuts it into two parts is said to be simply connected. The manifolds with which we will be concerned are simply connected.

5 This example is from A. d'Abro, The Evolution of Scientific Thought, Dover, 1950.

6 Given a graded gray wire, the gray and the metal are one-dimensional manifolds, and so is the combination. We need to be mindful of what features we are considering.

7 For example, the visual field is coarser toward the periphery. Another example: two pin pricks on the skin, when very close together, are experienced as a single prick.

8 The distance relation satisfies the following conditions. Let d(P,Q) be the distance between P and Q, then:

d(P,P) = 0, d(P,Q) > 0 if P ≠ Q

d(P,Q) = d(Q,P)

d(P,Q) + d(Q,R) > d(P,R)

9 For example, the immediate visual field is not homogeneous. Visual acuity at the periphery of the visual field is much lower than at the center. The kinesthetic space of arm movements is not isotropic. Extending an arm feels different from moving it sideways.

10 H.H. Price, "Survival and the idea of 'another world"', Proc. Soc. Psychical Research, 1953, pp. 11-12.

11 Poincaré,Mathematics and Science: Last Essays, Ch. 3.

12 Although these operations can generate contiguity and extension in a visual or kinesthetic field, these features of a field are not sufficient for the perceptual unity which is present in consciousness, and the binding problem is not solved.

Read More...

Saturday, October 21, 2006

Speculations on the Brains and Minds of Cetaceans

Huntley Ingalls headshot by Huntley Ingalls

"Genius in the sperm whale? Has the sperm whale ever written a book, spoken a speech? No, his great genius is declared in doing nothing in particular to prove it. It is moreover declared in his pyramidical silence. And this reminds me that had the great sperm whale been known to the Orient World, he would have been deified by their child-magician thoughts…

"Champollion deciphered the wrinkled granite hieroglyphics. But there is no Champollion to decipher the Egypt of every man's and every being's face….If then, Sir William Jones, who read in thirty languages, could not read the simplest peasant's face in its profounder and more subtle meanings, how may unlettered Ishmael hope to read the awful chaldee of the sperm whale's brow? I but put that brow before you. Read it if you can.

"My object here is simply to project the draught of a systematization of cetology….But it is a ponderous task"to grope down into the bottom of the sea after them; to have one's hands among the unspeakable foundations, ribs, and very pelvis of the world; this is a fearful thing. What am I that I should essay to hook the nose of this leviathan!" - Herman Melville

Anyone familiar with the brains of higher mammals is shocked when first confronted with the physical appearance of the cetacean brain. Its size, globular shape, and elaborate convolutions suggest what might be imagined as the brain of a superior being. The typical weight of a human brain is about three pounds, of a dolphin about 3.5, of a large baleen whale 13, and of a sperm whale 20. The convolutions of the cetacean brain are far more elaborate than those of the human brain. The density of neurons and the complexity of neural connections in the two brains are comparable. The thickness of the cetacean neocortex is less than that of the human, but its greater surface area supports, in some species, an equal or greater number of nerve cells. The early whales of Eocene times, about 50 million years ago, were fully aquatic but had small, primitive brains. Large-brained cetaceans appeared about 30 million years ago, and large-brained humanoids about 5 million years ago. The greater length of evolution for the cetacean brain is not proof of greater advancement, but it is a startling suggestion of refinement.

Brains are metabolically expensive and such huge neural systems cannot be mere embellishments. They are unnecessary for simply operating a large marine animal. The whale shark, which is sometimes 50 feet long, does well with its primitive fish brain. The enormous development of the cetacean brain has evolved through survival advantage or social selection and must support functions of great importance to whales. We will try here to imagine the possible nature of these functions. Most of the ideas presented are highly speculative, but at least some of them are testable in principle. Even wrong ideas are often valuable if they can stimulate further thought or suggest experiments and tests which sharpen old conceptual landscapes or illuminate new ones.

Whales have limited ability for physically manipulating objects. This alone would form their minds differently from human minds, because our concept of objects and physical space is greatly influenced by kinesthetic interaction with the environment. As far as can be determined, sound is the only familiar sensory mode in which they are extensively involved. This is a very effective sense mode for life in the water. Sound travels farther and 4 1/2 times faster in water than in air, is little affected by murkiness or depth, is an excellent means of echolocating objects and an excellent medium for socialization. Thus it seems quite likely that very elaborate sound processing is a major function of the large cetacean brain. A large part of the human brain is involved in processing visual information. Light waves vary in length from about 4 to 8 hundred thousandths of a centimeter, but sound waves used by cetaceans vary from about a centimeter to over 70 meters. Perhaps the relative physical grossness of sound would require more neurons and cell assemblies in order to process sound data with a resolution of detail approaching that of vision.

Whatever intelligence cetaceans may have appears to be different from ours. This is indicated by the ease with which they are killed by whalers or trapped in fishing nets. Yet the size and complexity of their brains indicate enormous activity and possibly an extraordinary rich mental life. Their mental life is probably much more involved with social relationships than problem solving. The intelligence of dolphins is indicated by their love of play, complex social behavior, and the ease with which they learn tricks in captivity. Gregory Bateson1has shown that dolphins not only can learn new tricks, but also can learn that they are supposed to learn a new trick in new sessions. The new trick may even be the negative of behavior which was rewarded earlier. He notes that the dolphin cannot do this by conditioning from a single sample, but must do it from the structure of a complex sample. This kind of learning operates on a higher logical level than learning from the repetition of a type of instance.

Humpback whales sing complicated songs that are as long as half an hour. The songs evolve from year to year, indicating an impressive memory. The whales do not sing in their summer feeding grounds, but they begin the previous season's songs when they return to their winter grounds and gradually change them as the season progresses. They are able to memorize all the complicated sounds of a song, as well as new modification, for at least six months as a basis for further improvisations.

Man's brain
Figure 1. Brain size is a rather crude indicator of brain capacity, and a man's (above) is by no means the largest at 1,450 grams. For instance, the brain of the dolphin weighs 1,700 grams, and that of the adult fin whale (left) weighs 6 to 7 kilograms (From Donald B. Tower, 1954, Journal of Comparative Neurology 101:27.)

Animal brain sizes
Figure 2. The comparative size of the brain in the dog, orangutang, human, and sperm whale. Note especially the development of the cerebrum.

The cetacean brain has evolved in a simpler, less kinesthetically manipulable, and less demanding environment than that in which the human brain arose. This contrast is reflected in the different organizations of the two brains. The lamination and regional differentiation of the cerebral cortex are comparably developed in both species, although differently arranged. In cetaceans the areas of the cortex receiving information from sense organs, especially those representing the ears and face, are very large. Motor control occupies less cortical area than in the human brain, indicating orientation more toward perception and less toward action and motor skills than in humans.

Each hemisphere of the human brain has three basic, concentric formations representing successive stages of neural evolution. The innermost and oldest, the rhinic lobe, supports the basic survival functions. The middle, or limbic lobe, is the seat of emotional activity and motivation. The third and largest, the supralimbic lobe, is the seat of rational processes. Cetaceans have a fourth formation, the paralimbic lobe, between the limbic and supralimbic lobes. This is a unique, very large feature not found in other mammals, a specialized region in which all sensory and motor areas are represented together. In the human brain the different sensory areas are widely separated. For example, the motor area lies next to the touch area but is separated from all other sensory regions. An integrated perception of sight, sound, and touch is dependent on electrical impulses in the neurons that travel long distances in which time and information are lost. Apparently, the paralimbic lobe supports the very rapid formation of integrated perceptions.

It has been suggested that the scattering of sense projection areas in the human brain evolved from the need for quick danger response. Each of the sensory areas is bordered by interpretation areas which deal with only one sense. When a sound suggesting danger is registered, the neural system signals alarm before receiving visual conformation. Neither does vision wait for sound or touch. Our intellectual functions are based on these separate sense interpretation areas. Perhaps this favors abstract thought in the human mind, while the paralimbic lobe favors an immensely rich apperception. If the cetacean brain has fewer separate association areas, the cetacean mind may have a smaller variety of concepts. It would be more difficult for whales to have abstract ideas because there would be less variety of basically different things to compare. Hence they would tend to have less problem solving ability and less intelligence than humans, although not less, and possibly greater, cerebral activity.

A. In whales and dolphins, the areas of cerebral cortex receiving sensory inputs and initiating motor responses are distributed along the medial wall of each hemisphere. This meiobasal view of the right hemisphere of the bottlenose dolphin shows the highly folded and continuous nature of this sensorimotor cortex. bottlenose dolphin meiobasal view of right brain hemisphere
bottlenose dolphin dorsal view of brain B. Dorsal view of the brain of the bottlenose dolphin covered by a filmy layer of meningers to show the high degree of folding of the cerebral cortex which results in a surface area of the enocortex that is greater than in man.
C. Lateral view of brain of the bottlenose dolphin (Tursiops truncatus) emphasizing the richness of cortical folding and showing the characteristic foreshortening and increased height of the cetacean brain. bottlenose dolphin lateral view of brain
bottlenose dolphin basal view of brain D. Basal view of the brain of the bottlenose dolphin (Tursiops truncatus) which, in the adult, weighs about 1600 grams. Emphasized is the cerebellum which, in Cetaceans, may comprise up to 20 percent of the total brain weight, considerably more than most other mammals, including man (about 12 percent). The intact pituitary gland is also shown in position, near the middle of the rain in this picture.
E. This medial view of the right half of the brain of the bottlenose dolphin shows clearly the continuity of sensorimotor areas of the paralimbic lobe. The dashed lines are superimposed over deep clefts that demarcate this lobe sharply from the rest of the hemisphere. bottlenose dolphin medial view of brain
Figures 3.A - 3.E. Cut-away images of bottlenose dolphin brain structure.

Sterling Bunnel, a psychiatrist, suggested that the evolution of the large cetacean brain originated in the needs of river dolphins to find their way about by echolocation in the murky waters of rivers and estuaries.2The Ganges River dolphin is blind. In rainy seasons it leaves the river, pursuing fish through flooded forests in very turbid water. It is necessary in these rangings to form detailed maps to prevent being trapped by receding waters. Thus the auditory and tactile senses and the general association areas of the brain in which memories are stored have become highly developed. It is true that small-brained bats have good echolocation for capturing insects and for navigating in caves, but sonic memory maps are not needed to capture insects and bats spend only a few minutes each day navigating to and from their fixed roosts. The very early whales, which evolved from land animals that adapted to the sea, had small brains. If large-brained whales evolved in the rivers and estuaries, they could have returned to the sea and replaced the more primitive whales. In the sea the cetacean brain entered a second stage of evolution and continued to increase in size. The continuing increase may have been a result of social selection, because the demands of survival in the marine environment do not seem sufficient to evolve such huge brains. Elephants have a complex social life, and their brains may have evolved through social selection after their great size made their lives more free of danger. Our own large brains may have evolved not only from the advantages of problem solving ability and deceptive behavior, but also from social selection of desirable psychic qualities such as empathy and sensitivity. Highly developed social interaction, including deception, requires the ability to image, model, and remember the psychic state of other beings, and such ability requires a very large amount of neural activity.

Bunnell3believes that the cetacean's senses and great memory capacity, developed for navigation in murky water, are ideally pre-adapted for social communication. The echolocation apparatus not only can project complex signals, but has the capability for detailed three-dimensional perception of the physical and emotional state of another cetacean's entire body. Echoes arise from the interior body as well as the skin of another cetacean. Actually, stronger echoes arise from the air-filled cavities and the bone of an animal than from the skin. This enables the pulsations of the vessels and viscera, and hence the emotional state and health of an animal, to be easily perceived, adding a new dimension of social interaction.

Thus the need for elaborate sound processing is the most likely reason for the great development of the cetacean brain. Sound is used very extensively by cetaceans, and water is much more pervaded by sound than light. Sam Ridgway, a dolphin researcher at the Naval Ocean Systems Center in San Diego, believes that much of the great development of the dolphin auditory system is a result of a need for great precision and speed in processing sound.4But surely dolphins are also processing more sound data and processing them far more elaborately than bats or owls. Indeed, if sound data are to be processed into sensory field comparable to vision, the data would need to be processed very rapidly and precisely. Let us consider in more detail some of the possible uses of elaborate sound processing.

The two basic possible uses for elaborate sound processing are communication and perception. The whale's environment does not seem sufficiently complex to require a vast amount of information communication. But the possibilities for social communication and selection of feelings, emotions, and aesthetic sound patterns are extremely rich. It seems likely that they frolic with their minds as well as with their bodies. Perhaps they can create sound so elaborate, beautiful, and satisfying that they have selected that capability just as birds of paradise have selected spectacular feathers. Such feathers have no survival advantage and no severe disadvantage in a benign environment, but they are strongly preferred by the birds. There are occasions when animals do act for immediate satisfactions. This is vividly demonstrated by the extreme case of self-stimulation, to exhaustion, by rats which are able to activate electrodes implanted in the pleasure centers of their brains. When an action is not automatic as breathing, reflex, or nest building by insects, it may be done for pleasure or avoidance of pain rather than for some direct survival advantage. The survival purpose of an action may arise secondarily rather than by choice. When young animals play, they are not aware that they are developing social and survival skills. Elaborate behavior or effects may be selected for gratification when there is no definite survival disadvantage.

It is possible that whales use advanced sound forms and are involved in aesthetics that are inconceivable to us. The functions of the paralimbic lobe may have the effect of fusing the various senses in the manner that hearing speech fuses sound and meaning. The areas of the human brain that process sound and meaning lie close together. We do not hear a word and then translate it unless we are struggling with a new language. We hear meaning. Thus the cetacean's senses may be fused by the paralimbic lobe to produce a direct apperception of a richness and beauty unknown to us.

Bunnell5notes that vision is a special sense which gives simultaneous information in the form of pictures with poor time discrimination, and that our auditory sense has very limited space perception but good time discrimination. Thus our languages are composed of sounds in temporal sequences. He suggests that the cetacean auditory system is essentially spatial with much simultaneous information. Cetacean communication apparently consists of complex sounds perceived as a unit. These communications are probably not a syntactical language of technical information or abstract concepts. Perhaps they project ideograms representing entire social situations, elaborate emotions, extensive sequences of events presented as a picture, or all of these in one extraordinary unit. The paralimbic lobe may well have enormous memory capacity, which would expand potential size and complexity of an ideographic vocabulary. Bunnel further speculates that the cetacean echolocation system produces detailed images of objects, and that perhaps they can recreate these sounds and directly project sonic images to one another.

Projection of images of one's bodily state, past, present, and future, and of the states of others would be a powerful way of expressing feelings and emotions. Cetacean language may be somewhat similar to Chinese ideograms in which pictures are equated to ideas. It may be possible to confirm some of these conjectures by comparing audiograms of reflected and projected sounds. Similar patterns in the sounds would indicate communication of perceptions, especially if the patterns were very complex. The social, emotional and aesthetic life of humans would be greatly enriched by the ability to project visual images to others that would be as detailed as the actual viewing of an object, scene, or situation.

The fusing of received and projected sonic messages with other sensory experiences has vast possibilities for aesthetic and social experience. Some idea of what this may be like is suggested by the special experience of eye contact. They are special because quick, subtle movements and light changes interact within the actual time of the mental processes. Such real time interplay is much diminished in communication through delayed serial clusters of speech. The intimate interactions of eye contact seem to fuse with the emotions of the moment. The nature of sound allows perception from all directions and makes it possible for more than two cetaceans to enter into such communication. If three or more people could engage in eye contact at the same time, could generate and project meaningful patterns of light both bodily and ideographically, all in real time and fused as intimately as meaning and sound are fused in speech, then humans might have experiences similar to the possibilities of cetacean social life.

The other major use for elaborate sound processing is location and perception of objects. The sperm whale has the largest brain of all and it is also the only whale which dives to great depths for prey, at least to 3600 feet and possibly to two miles. This is certainly an environment in which sonic echolocation and very detailed sophisticated sonic perception would be of prime usefulness, especially since the whale can remain at such great depths for less than 45 minutes. The obvious usefulness of sonic perception at great depths is consistent with the sperm whale's great increase in brain size. This may be a third step in the evolution of the cetacean brain. The enormous neural development for social life, which may have arisen after river dolphins returned to sea, would be a natural basis for further evolution needed for deep diving.

Our basic visual field is two-dimensional, which can be appreciated by looking at bright light with closed eyes. The third dimension of visual space is given by a system of distance values assigned through elaborate cues, such as ocular convergence, binocular disparity, texture density gradients, motion parallax, superposition, and illumination direction. Another three-dimensional sensory space is the kinesthetic space in which is experienced when moving about in a dark room. This space is much more highly developed in blind people. We have a poorly developed sonic space because the sound elements have very little connectivity, although a continuous, rapidly varying pitch can give a suggestive glimmer of a one-dimensional sonic space. Blind people are able to make remarkable use of sound for gauging their surroundings, but this is not a sonic space. It is rather a kinesthetic space closely associated with sonic data. Sensory spaces are not physical space, although they are coordinated with it. Visual space can be distorted by lenses, drugs, or brain injury, but physical space is distorted only by extreme conditions, such as very powerful gravitational fields, which are not encountered in ordinary life.

It seems possible that, if cetaceans can assign definite directions to sounds, they can convert sound stimuli into neural patterns that generate a three-dimensional sonic sensory space. If this is true, then the whale would experience itself immersed in a three-dimensional sonic space similar to our immersion in three-dimensional. That is, it would "see" with sound. The immediate sonic field would probably surround the whale, unlike our immediate visual field which is in front of us, although the greatest clarity and acuity would be in front because the head region is better innervated for sound reception. The head is also the source of sound projection, and the echoes of projected sound are more unidirectional in the high frequencies.

Objects would be located in this space as we locate objects in visual space. There would be both sources and reflectors of sound, just as there are emitters and reflectors of light in the visual world. If sound has sufficiently high frequency, it can be reflected with such coherence that an object, e. g., a fish, would be perceived as a fish in a manner comparable to our seeing a fish. The selective reflectivity of different frequencies by various kinds of objects might even be perceived as qualities analogous to color.

The cetacean's sonic space would differ structurally from human visual space. Perception in sonic space would have less acuity than in visual space and the acuity would vary with the frequency of the sound. The distance range of detectable sound in water varies from a few feet for extremely high frequencies to many miles for very low frequencies. There is a noticeable time delay of one second per 5000 feet in the transmission of sound in water. The frequency of sound from a source is increased or decreased by the Doppler effect when the source moves toward or away from the observer. In contrast, perception in visual space is much sharper, has practically the same acuity and range for all wavelengths of visible light, and has no time delay or Doppler effect in ordinary life. These differences between sonic and visual spaces are evident because sound is far slower than light and has greater wavelengths. An object cannot reflect a wave whose length is greater than the size of the object. Dolphins can emit and detect sounds at least as high as 120,000 cycles per second. Sound at that pitch can be used to detect objects as small as an inch. This is a resolution of about 7 minutes of arc at 20 feet, although proportionally less at closer distances. Dolphins can also determine the direction at this sound with about the same accuracy. It is possible that the dolphin can use even higher frequencies which would give still better resolution. The resolution of human vision is about a minute of arc. It is also quite possible that the dolphin combines its sonic and visual spaces into a single sensory space which would have more structural uniformity and better resolution at close ranges. Combining these spaces may be one of the functions of the paralimbic lobe.

Far more must be known about the mechanism for generating visual space from the neural activity of the visual cortex before we can understand the manner, or even the possibility, of generating a sonic space. Even then we may know if the quality of the space is sonic or visual, i. e., whether it would be occupied by sound or by visual sensa supported by sonic input. All mental activity is based on electrical impulses in nerve cells, and all types of these cells have the same kind of impulse. The sensory quality of an experience depends on the processing and organization of the impulses. If the nerves of the inner ear were connected to the visual cortex, sounds would be experienced with a visual quality.

Cetaceans do not have an organ concentrating an array of sound detectors similar to the array of rods and cones in the retina. Dolphins have two inner ears that receive sound via fatty deposits inside the jawbone and a region of the forehead called the melon that possibly functions as a sonic focusing device. If they experience a sonic space of two or more dimensions by means of this apparatus, that space must be supported by some means of storing the data as they are received through the two ears. Somewhat analogously, the visual impressions from the moving spot of light that scans the surface of a television tube is held by the observer through persistence of vision for about 1/10 of a second, long enough for the scan to cover the entire tube and enable the observer to experience an image. If this were not so, we could perceive only a moving spot. The dolphin's two inner ears cannot construct a two-dimensional field from a fixed position, but head movement, swimming, and deliberate beaming of emitted sound in different directions could generate variations sufficient to support such a field. These movements would also widen the perceptual field for the high frequencies. It is also possible that cetaceans can detect sound through pressure variations on the skin. If this is the case, it might be possible for them to have a two-dimensional space of sensations via an array of sensors extending over the body surface. Such an array has the advantage of greater sonic data input for a given time interval, and data based on the array is more easily organized into a sensory space of more than one dimension.

Huntley Ingalls and friends
Huntley Ingalls and friends

The field of vision is experienced as a coherent continuum. This seemingly simple property cannot arise from a mere array of sensory elements alone. There must be some process which binds the elements, or they would be independent and would not appear together as a single expanse. This coherent field of vision may be supported by some sort of neural scanning mechanism. This is suggested by an interesting visual effect which can be induced by a flashing stroboscopic light. When an observer looks at such a light flashing between 6 and 30 times per second, his visual field becomes filled with complex, changing patterns such as dark or colored zigzag lines vibrating on a light background. Other patterns may be like the spokes of a wheel or a whirlpool. The zigzag lines may sweep from one side of the visual field to the other or form intricate mosaics. These effects do not come from the retina. This was demonstrated by Gray Walter,6a physiologist, who found that the electrical pulsations in the retina show no unusual effects under such flashing stroboscopic lights. Similar phenomena occur on a television screen when a studio illuminated by a flashing light is monitored by a television camera. Complex patterns of dots and lines dart and zigzag across the screen. This happens because the moving electron beam is scanning the screen to form the picture can illuminate the screen only during the very short intervals when the light is on in the studio. Thus only disconnected bits of the beam's rapid path over the screen are visible. The particular form of the patterns depend on the particular nature of the scanning mechanism. Possibly the whirling spiral that is often seen under stroboscopic flicker indicates the type of scan in the neural system which supports the visual field. This scan is not, of course, anything like a moving electron beam. It would perhaps be some sort of rhythmical firing of banks of nerve cells.

If an organism has a two-dimensional sensory field supported by a neural scanning mechanism, such a mechanism might be detected by electrodes in an appropriate part of the brain which can register the scan's electronic signature. If the firing of banks of cells in the visual cortex of a mammal has some characteristic erratic signature under stroboscopic light flashing at critical frequency, such a signature may also characterize other two-dimensional sensory fields and could be used to test for their existence. If this is the case and a dolphin were subjected to extremely short bursts of sound at constant critical intervals, and erratic firing of banks of auditory cells, similar to that of visual cells under stroboscopic flicker, might become evident. If the sonic data under the scan are stored longer than the duration of a single complete scan, then the sonic field could be two-dimensional with elaboration to three dimensions through cues such as the Doppler effect, modification of sound reflections by the shape and texture of surfaces, and by differential time delays of reflection from objects at various distances.

Suppose a two-dimensional space of sonic data with its three-dimensional cues can be held in storage for a few seconds while other, similar three-dimensional spaces are rapidly and continuously constructed and stored. The fields might be stored by repeated firing of banks of cells. Suppose further that a higher scan surveys this continuum of three-dimensional spaces and integrates them into a single manifold. This would have the effect of a four-dimensional sensory space in which span of time would have a spatial representation. Such a feat would require and enormous neural system. This conjecture is, of course, very speculative, but here may be some natural base for such a development. The huge supralimbic and paralimbic lobes of cetaceans very likely have enormous memory capacity, and if they store data to support sonic fields, this could be a base for a next stage of perception. If cetaceans do experience three-dimensional sonic spaces, then some survival or social advantage for another dimension of sonic space might induce such a development. The sperm whale's largest brain size suggests the greatest development for processing sonic data. If there is any survival advantage to the ability to experience four-dimensional sonic space, it may well be associated with deep diving.

It is not certain that this ability would be of any technical advantage to the whale. The sperm whale's limited time at great depths must be spent very efficiently to capture enough prey to support so large a creature. A capacity for four-dimensional sonic perception would allow it to perceive the trajectories of its prey imaging dynamic processes that would enable it to capture prey more effectively. Possibly a whale would also be able to monitor the activities of other prey while it is actually feeding. Such perception has an advantage at great depths because there is no continuous field of contiguous objects such as we experience in our daily life, but separate objects moving about in a sonically dark, or relatively dark, background. A four-dimensional sensory space would be most effective if its span represented a few seconds. A longer span would clutter perception. A whale's aesthetic and social life would be enormously enhanced by a four-dimensional sonic space. Perhaps they could create music, sonic arabesques and sculpture, or social messages beyond our comprehension.

Humans experience a slight, crude four-dimensional visual space. This is manifest when we see the trajectory of a rapidly moving light in a dark room. We would be unable to see a picture on a television screen if our perceptions were strictly from instant to instant. We would see only a series of dots as the electron beam scanned the tube. The slight persistence of hearing combined with the running memory enables us to experience rhythms. Thus we operate in a crude four-dimensional space, but its span represents only 1/10 of a second.

If tests indicate that cetaceans experience sonic fields, it may be possible to make tests indicating four-dimensional sonic perception. This might be done by implanting electrodes in the auditory region of a cetacean's brain and presenting objects for it to echolocate which arouse a definite electronic signature. The rapid repetition of the signature for a sustained time would suggest a four-dimensional sonic perception. That is, we might try to determine of a sound pattern "reverberates" in the cetacean's brain. In another possibility, a signature might be linked to a very transient event, such as an abrupt change of direction by a darting squid, and the time span of the event found to be less than that of the signature repetition.

Cetaceans may be less proficient problem solvers than humans, but they surely have enormous cerebral activity. A creature is a being when it experiences a conscious sensory field, and is a person when it has a concept of the self and an awareness of its own self. The self may have arisen from the needs for survival planning by problem solving creatures in dangerous environments. If this is true, then cetaceans are less likely that humanoids to have selves. But the sense of self would enrich cetacean life and would be very useful in social competition. If cetaceans' sonic transmissions contain some symbol for the sender and for each individual, i. E., a name, personhood would be suggested. All cetaceans are almost certainly beings. Perhaps some are prodigious beings, and conceivably persons.

Boulder, Colorado (1992)

Child next to whale
Head-To-Head

1 "Observations of Cetacean Community," Gregory Bateson in Mind in the Waters. Assembled by John McIntyer. Scribners/Sierra Club, 1974.

2 "The Evolution of Cetacean Intelligence," Sterling Bunnell in Mind in the Waters. Assembled by John McIntyer. Scribners/Sierra Club, 1974.

3 Op. Cit., "The Evolution of Cetacean Intelligence."

4 "Physiological Observations on Dolphin Brains." Sam H. Ridgway in Dolphin Cognition and Behavior: A Comparative Approach. R. Schusterman, J. Thomas, and F. Wood (Eds.). Lawrence Erlaum associates, Hillsdale, new Jersey, 1986.

5 Op. Cit., "The Evolution of Cetacean Intelligence."

6 The Living Brain. Gray Walter. P. 102. Norton, 1953.

Read More...